Jensen hierarchy

From The Right Wiki
Revision as of 04:07, 24 September 2024 by imported>RhubarbJayde
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)
Jump to navigationJump to search

In set theory, a mathematical discipline, the Jensen hierarchy or J-hierarchy is a modification of Gödel's constructible hierarchy, L, that circumvents certain technical difficulties that exist in the constructible hierarchy. The J-Hierarchy figures prominently in fine structure theory, a field pioneered by Ronald Jensen, for whom the Jensen hierarchy is named. Rudimentary functions describe a method for iterating through the Jensen hierarchy.

Definition

As in the definition of L, let Def(X) be the collection of sets definable with parameters over X:

Def(X):={{yXΦ(y,z1,...,zn) is true in (X,)}Φ is a first order formula,z1,...,znX}

The constructible hierarchy, L is defined by transfinite recursion. In particular, at successor ordinals, Lα+1=Def(Lα). The difficulty with this construction is that each of the levels is not closed under the formation of unordered pairs; for a given x,yLα+1Lα, the set {x,y} will not be an element of Lα+1, since it is not a subset of Lα. However, Lα does have the desirable property of being closed under Σ0 separation.[1] Jensen's modification of the L hierarchy retains this property and the slightly weaker condition that Jα+1𝒫(Jα)=Def(Jα), but is also closed under pairing. The key technique is to encode hereditarily definable sets over Jα by codes; then Jα+1 will contain all sets whose codes are in Jα. Like Lα, Jα is defined recursively. For each ordinal α, we define Wnα to be a universal Σn predicate for Jα. We encode hereditarily definable sets as Xα(n+1,e)={Xα(n,f)Wn+1α(e,f)}, with Xα(0,e)=e. Then set Jα,n:={Xα(n,e)eJα} and finally, Jα+1:=nωJα,n.

Properties

Each sublevel Jα, n is transitive and contains all ordinals less than or equal to ωα + n. The sequence of sublevels is strictly ⊆-increasing in n, since a Σm predicate is also Σn for any n > m. The levels Jα will thus be transitive and strictly ⊆-increasing as well, and are also closed under pairing, Δ0-comprehension and transitive closure. Moreover, they have the property that

Jα+1𝒫(Jα)=Def(Jα),

as desired. (Or a bit more generally, Lω+α=J1+αVω+α.[2]) The levels and sublevels are themselves Σ1 uniformly definable (i.e. the definition of Jα, n in Jβ does not depend on β), and have a uniform Σ1 well-ordering. Also, the levels of the Jensen hierarchy satisfy a condensation lemma much like the levels of Gödel's original hierarchy. For any Jα, considering any Σn relation on Jα, there is a Skolem function for that relation that is itself definable by a Σn formula.[3]

Rudimentary functions

A rudimentary function is a Vn→V function (i.e. a finitary function accepting sets as arguments) that can be obtained from the following operations:[2]

  • F(x1, x2, ...) = xi is rudimentary (see projection function)
  • F(x1, x2, ...) = {xi, xj} is rudimentary
  • F(x1, x2, ...) = xixj is rudimentary
  • Any composition of rudimentary functions is rudimentary
  • zyG(z, x1, x2, ...) is rudimentary, where G is a rudimentary function

For any set M let rud(M) be the smallest set containing M∪{M} closed under the rudimentary functions. Then the Jensen hierarchy satisfies Jα+1 = rud(Jα).[2]

Projecta

Jensen defines ραn, the Σn projectum of α, as the largest βα such that (Jβ,A) is amenable for all AΣn(Jα)𝒫(Jβ), and the Δn projectum of α is defined similarly. One of the main results of fine structure theory is that ραn is also the largest γ such that not every Σn(Jα) subset of ωγ is (in the terminology of α-recursion theory) α-finite.[2] Lerman defines the Sn projectum of α to be the largest γ such that not every Sn subset of β is α-finite, where a set is Sn if it is the image of a function f(x) expressible as limy1limy2limyng(x,y1,y2,,yn) where g is α-recursive. In a Jensen-style characterization, S3 projectum of α is the largest βα such that there is an S3 epimorphism from β onto α. There exists an ordinal α whose Δ3 projectum is ω, but whose Sn projectum is α for all natural n. [4]

References

  1. Wolfram Pohlers, Proof Theory: The First Step Into Impredicativity (2009) (p.247)
  2. 2.0 2.1 2.2 2.3 K. Devlin, An introduction to the fine structure of the constructible hierarchy (1974). Accessed 2022-02-26.
  3. R. B. Jensen, The Fine Structure of the Constructible Hierarchy (1972), p.247. Accessed 13 January 2023.
  4. S. G. Simpson, "Short course on admissible recursion theory". Appearing in Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics vol. 94, Generalized Recursion Theory II (1978), pp.355--390
  • Sy Friedman (2000) Fine Structure and Class Forcing, Walter de Gruyter, ISBN 3-11-016777-8