Well-quasi-ordering

From The Right Wiki
(Redirected from Well partial order)
Jump to navigationJump to search
Transitive binary relations
Symmetric Antisymmetric Connected Well-founded Has joins Has meets Reflexive Irreflexive Asymmetric
Total, Semiconnex Anti-
reflexive
Equivalence relation Green tickY Green tickY
Preorder (Quasiorder) Green tickY
Partial order Green tickY Green tickY
Total preorder Green tickY Green tickY
Total order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
Prewellordering Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
Well-quasi-ordering Green tickY Green tickY
Well-ordering Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
Lattice Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
Join-semilattice Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
Meet-semilattice Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
Strict partial order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
Strict weak order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
Strict total order Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY Green tickY
Symmetric Antisymmetric Connected Well-founded Has joins Has meets Reflexive Irreflexive Asymmetric
Definitions, for all a,b and S: aRbbRa aRb and bRaa=b abaRb or bRa minSexists abexists abexists aRa not aRa aRbnot bRa
Green tickY indicates that the column's property is always true for the row's term (at the very left), while indicates that the property is not guaranteed in general (it might, or might not, hold). For example, that every equivalence relation is symmetric, but not necessarily antisymmetric, is indicated by Green tickY in the "Symmetric" column and in the "Antisymmetric" column, respectively.

All definitions tacitly require the homogeneous relation R be transitive: for all a,b,c, if aRb and bRc then aRc.
A term's definition may require additional properties that are not listed in this table.

In mathematics, specifically order theory, a well-quasi-ordering or wqo on a set X is a quasi-ordering of X for which every infinite sequence of elements x0,x1,x2, from X contains an increasing pair xixj with i<j.

Motivation

Well-founded induction can be used on any set with a well-founded relation, thus one is interested in when a quasi-order is well-founded. (Here, by abuse of terminology, a quasiorder is said to be well-founded if the corresponding strict order xyyx is a well-founded relation.) However the class of well-founded quasiorders is not closed under certain operations—that is, when a quasi-order is used to obtain a new quasi-order on a set of structures derived from our original set, this quasiorder is found to be not well-founded. By placing stronger restrictions on the original well-founded quasiordering one can hope to ensure that our derived quasiorderings are still well-founded. An example of this is the power set operation. Given a quasiordering for a set X one can define a quasiorder + on X's power set P(X) by setting A+B if and only if for each element of A one can find some element of B that is larger than it with respect to . One can show that this quasiordering on P(X) needn't be well-founded, but if one takes the original quasi-ordering to be a well-quasi-ordering, then it is.

Formal definition

A well-quasi-ordering on a set X is a quasi-ordering (i.e., a reflexive, transitive binary relation) such that any infinite sequence of elements x0,x1,x2, from X contains an increasing pair xixj with i<j. The set X is said to be well-quasi-ordered, or shortly wqo. A well partial order, or a wpo, is a wqo that is a proper ordering relation, i.e., it is antisymmetric. Among other ways of defining wqo's, one is to say that they are quasi-orderings which do not contain infinite strictly decreasing sequences (of the form x0>x1>x2>)[1] nor infinite sequences of pairwise incomparable elements. Hence a quasi-order (X, ≤) is wqo if and only if (X, <) is well-founded and has no infinite antichains.

Ordinal type

Let X be well partially ordered. A (necessarily finite) sequence (x1,x2,,xn) of elements of X that contains no pair xixj with i<j is usually called a bad sequence. The tree of bad sequences TX is the tree that contains a vertex for each bad sequence, and an edge joining each nonempty bad sequence (x1,,xn1,xn) to its parent (x1,,xn1). The root of TX corresponds to the empty sequence. Since X contains no infinite bad sequence, the tree TX contains no infinite path starting at the root.[citation needed] Therefore, each vertex v of TX has an ordinal height o(v), which is defined by transfinite induction as o(v)=limwchildofv(o(w)+1). The ordinal type of X, denoted o(X), is the ordinal height of the root of TX. A linearization of X is an extension of the partial order into a total order. It is easy to verify that o(X) is an upper bound on the ordinal type of every linearization of X. De Jongh and Parikh[1] proved that in fact there always exists a linearization of X that achieves the maximal ordinal type o(X).

Examples

File:Integers-line.svg
Pic.1: Integer numbers with the usual order
File:Infinite lattice of divisors.svg
Pic.2: Hasse diagram of the natural numbers ordered by divisibility
File:N-Quadrat, gedreht.svg
Pic.3: Hasse diagram of 2 with componentwise order
  • (,), the set of natural numbers with standard ordering, is a well partial order (in fact, a well-order). However, (,), the set of positive and negative integers, is not a well-quasi-order, because it is not well-founded (see Pic.1).
  • (,|), the set of natural numbers ordered by divisibility, is not a well-quasi-order: the prime numbers are an infinite antichain (see Pic.2).
  • (k,), the set of vectors of k natural numbers (where k is finite) with component-wise ordering, is a well partial order (Dickson's lemma; see Pic.3). More generally, if (X,) is well-quasi-order, then (Xk,k) is also a well-quasi-order for all k.
  • Let X be an arbitrary finite set with at least two elements. The set X* of words over X ordered lexicographically (as in a dictionary) is not a well-quasi-order because it contains the infinite decreasing sequence b,ab,aab,aaab,. Similarly, X* ordered by the prefix relation is not a well-quasi-order, because the previous sequence is an infinite antichain of this partial order. However, X* ordered by the subsequence relation is a well partial order.[2] (If X has only one element, these three partial orders are identical.)
  • More generally, (X*,), the set of finite X-sequences ordered by embedding is a well-quasi-order if and only if (X,) is a well-quasi-order (Higman's lemma). Recall that one embeds a sequence u into a sequence v by finding a subsequence of v that has the same length as u and that dominates it term by term. When (X,=) is an unordered set, uv if and only if u is a subsequence of v.
  • (Xω,), the set of infinite sequences over a well-quasi-order (X,), ordered by embedding, is not a well-quasi-order in general. That is, Higman's lemma does not carry over to infinite sequences. Better-quasi-orderings have been introduced to generalize Higman's lemma to sequences of arbitrary lengths.
  • Embedding between finite trees with nodes labeled by elements of a wqo (X,) is a wqo (Kruskal's tree theorem).
  • Embedding between infinite trees with nodes labeled by elements of a wqo (X,) is a wqo (Nash-Williams' theorem).
  • Embedding between countable scattered linear order types is a well-quasi-order (Laver's theorem).
  • Embedding between countable boolean algebras is a well-quasi-order. This follows from Laver's theorem and a theorem of Ketonen.
  • Finite graphs ordered by a notion of embedding called "graph minor" is a well-quasi-order (Robertson–Seymour theorem).
  • Graphs of finite tree-depth ordered by the induced subgraph relation form a well-quasi-order,[3] as do the cographs ordered by induced subgraphs.[4]

Constructing new wpo's from given ones

Let X1 and X2 be two disjoint wpo sets. Let Y=X1X2, and define a partial order on Y by letting y1Yy2 if and only if y1,y2Xi for the same i{1,2} and y1Xiy2. Then Y is wpo, and o(Y)=o(X1)o(X2), where denotes natural sum of ordinals.[1] Given wpo sets X1 and X2, define a partial order on the Cartesian product Y=X1×X2, by letting (a1,a2)Y(b1,b2) if and only if a1X1b1 and a2X2b2. Then Y is wpo (this is a generalization of Dickson's lemma), and o(Y)=o(X1)o(X2), where denotes natural product of ordinals.[1] Given a wpo set X, let X* be the set of finite sequences of elements of X, partially ordered by the subsequence relation. Meaning, let (x1,,xn)X*(y1,,ym) if and only if there exist indices 1i1<<inm such that xjXyij for each 1jn. By Higman's lemma, X* is wpo. The ordinal type of X* is[1][5] o(X*)={ωωo(X)1,o(X) finite;ωωo(X)+1,o(X)=εα+n for some α and some finite n;ωωo(X),otherwise. Given a wpo set X, let T(X) be the set of all finite rooted trees whose vertices are labeled by elements of X. Partially order T(X) by the tree embedding relation. By Kruskal's tree theorem, T(X) is wpo. This result is nontrivial even for the case |X|=1 (which corresponds to unlabeled trees), in which case o(T(X)) equals the small Veblen ordinal. In general, for o(X) countable, we have the upper bound o(T(X))ϑ(Ωωo(X)) in terms of the ϑ ordinal collapsing function. (The small Veblen ordinal equals ϑ(Ωω) in this ordinal notation.)[6]

Wqo's versus well partial orders

In practice, the wqo's one manipulates are quite often not orderings (see examples above), and the theory is technically smoother[citation needed] if we do not require antisymmetry, so it is built with wqo's as the basic notion. On the other hand, according to Milner 1985, no real gain in generality is obtained by considering quasi-orders rather than partial orders... it is simply more convenient to do so. Observe that a wpo is a wqo, and that a wqo gives rise to a wpo between equivalence classes induced by the kernel of the wqo. For example, if we order by divisibility, we end up with nm if and only if n=±m, so that (,|)(,|).

Infinite increasing subsequences

If (X,) is wqo then every infinite sequence x0,x1,x2,, contains an infinite increasing subsequence xn0xn1xn2 (with n0<n1<n2<). Such a subsequence is sometimes called perfect. This can be proved by a Ramsey argument: given some sequence (xi)i, consider the set I of indexes i such that xi has no larger or equal xj to its right, i.e., with i<j. If I is infinite, then the I-extracted subsequence contradicts the assumption that X is wqo. So I is finite, and any xn with n larger than any index in I can be used as the starting point of an infinite increasing subsequence. The existence of such infinite increasing subsequences is sometimes taken as a definition for well-quasi-ordering, leading to an equivalent notion.

Properties of wqos

  • Given a quasiordering (X,) the quasiordering (P(X),+) defined by A+BaA,bB,ab is well-founded if and only if (X,) is a wqo.[7]
  • A quasiordering is a wqo if and only if the corresponding partial order (obtained by quotienting by xyxyyx) has no infinite descending sequences or antichains. (This can be proved using a Ramsey argument as above.)
  • Given a well-quasi-ordering (X,), any sequence of upward-closed subsets S0S1X eventually stabilises (meaning there exists n such that Sn=Sn+1=; a subset SX is called upward-closed if x,yX,xyxSyS): assuming the contrary i,j,j>i,xSjSi, a contradiction is reached by extracting an infinite non-ascending subsequence.
  • Given a well-quasi-ordering (X,), any subset S of X has a finite number of minimal elements with respect to , for otherwise the minimal elements of S would constitute an infinite antichain.

See also

Notes

^ Here x < y means: xy and xy.

References

  1. 1.0 1.1 1.2 1.3 de Jongh, Dick H. G.; Parikh, Rohit (1977). "Well-partial orderings and hierarchies". Indagationes Mathematicae (Proceedings). 80 (3): 195–207. doi:10.1016/1385-7258(77)90067-1.
  2. Gasarch, W. (1998), "A survey of recursive combinatorics", Handbook of Recursive Mathematics, Vol. 2, Stud. Logic Found. Math., vol. 139, Amsterdam: North-Holland, pp. 1041–1176, doi:10.1016/S0049-237X(98)80049-9, MR 1673598. See in particular page 1160.
  3. Nešetřil, Jaroslav; Ossona de Mendez, Patrice (2012), "Lemma 6.13", Sparsity: Graphs, Structures, and Algorithms, Algorithms and Combinatorics, vol. 28, Heidelberg: Springer, p. 137, doi:10.1007/978-3-642-27875-4, ISBN 978-3-642-27874-7, MR 2920058.
  4. Damaschke, Peter (1990), "Induced subgraphs and well-quasi-ordering", Journal of Graph Theory, 14 (4): 427–435, doi:10.1002/jgt.3190140406, MR 1067237.
  5. Schmidt, Diana (1979). Well-partial orderings and their maximal order types (Habilitationsschrift). Heidelberg. Republished in: Schmidt, Diana (2020). "Well-partial orderings and their maximal order types". In Schuster, Peter M.; Seisenberger, Monika; Weiermann, Andreas (eds.). Well-Quasi Orders in Computation, Logic, Language and Reasoning. Trends in Logic. Vol. 53. Springer. pp. 351–391. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-30229-0_13.
  6. Rathjen, Michael; Weiermann, Andreas (1993). "Proof-theoretic investigations on Kruskal's theorem". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 60: 49–88. doi:10.1016/0168-0072(93)90192-G.
  7. Forster, Thomas (2003). "Better-quasi-orderings and coinduction". Theoretical Computer Science. 309 (1–3): 111–123. doi:10.1016/S0304-3975(03)00131-2.